Home > Research > Publications & Outputs > Developing autonomy and transitional paternalism

Electronic data

  • Developing Autonomy and Transitional Paternalism_Accepted Author Manuscript

    Rights statement: This is the peer reviewed version of the following article: Tucker, F. (2016), Developing Autonomy and Transitional Paternalism. Bioethics, 30: 759–766. doi:10.1111/bioe.12280 which has been published in final form at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12280/abstract This article may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance With Wiley Terms and Conditions for self-archiving.

    Accepted author manuscript, 166 KB, PDF document

    Available under license: CC BY-NC: Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License

Links

Text available via DOI:

View graph of relations

Developing autonomy and transitional paternalism

Research output: Contribution to Journal/MagazineJournal articlepeer-review

Published

Standard

Developing autonomy and transitional paternalism. / Tucker, Faye.
In: Bioethics, Vol. 30, No. 9, 11.2016, p. 759-766.

Research output: Contribution to Journal/MagazineJournal articlepeer-review

Harvard

APA

Vancouver

Tucker F. Developing autonomy and transitional paternalism. Bioethics. 2016 Nov;30(9):759-766. Epub 2016 Sept 15. doi: 10.1111/bioe.12280

Author

Tucker, Faye. / Developing autonomy and transitional paternalism. In: Bioethics. 2016 ; Vol. 30, No. 9. pp. 759-766.

Bibtex

@article{c1feb87b8e854952b687c0b325ab171f,
title = "Developing autonomy and transitional paternalism",
abstract = "Adolescents, in many jurisdictions, have the power to consent to life saving treatment but not necessarily the power to refuse it. A recent defence of this asymmetry is Neil Manson's theory of {\textquoteleft}transitional paternalism{\textquoteright}. Transitional paternalism holds that such asymmetries are by-products of sharing normative powers. However, sharing normative powers by itself does not entail an asymmetry because transitional paternalism can be implemented in two ways. Manson defends the asymmetry-generating version of transitional paternalism in the clinical context, arguing that it maximizes respect for adolescent autonomy. This article offers an alternative argument in favour of the asymmetry-generating form of transitional paternalism, one that makes appeal to obligations that individuals have to develop self-governance in others. We should share normative powers asymmetrically in the clinical context for three reasons. First, the asymmetric version of transitional paternalism takes seriously duties to support adolescents{\textquoteright} developing autonomy, alongside other duties that adults have to young people. It does so by enabling young people to be involved in important decisions that they would otherwise be excluded from. This is of value because participation of this sort is central to the cultivation of their self-governance. Second, only the asymmetric version gives young people a voice in respect of all clinical actions, and only the asymmetric version leaves open the possibility that the coarse lines of legislation might be {\textquoteleft}fine-tuned{\textquoteright} in individual cases. Third, the asymmetric sharing of normative powers is consistent with the kind of social arrangements that best support autonomy.",
keywords = "asymmetry of consent, developing autonomy, decision-making, paternalism, adolescence, self-governance",
author = "Faye Tucker",
note = "This is the peer reviewed version of the following article: Tucker, F. (2016), Developing Autonomy and Transitional Paternalism. Bioethics, 30: 759–766. doi:10.1111/bioe.12280 which has been published in final form at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12280/abstract This article may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance With Wiley Terms and Conditions for self-archiving. ",
year = "2016",
month = nov,
doi = "10.1111/bioe.12280",
language = "English",
volume = "30",
pages = "759--766",
journal = "Bioethics",
issn = "1467-8519",
publisher = "Wiley-Blackwell",
number = "9",

}

RIS

TY - JOUR

T1 - Developing autonomy and transitional paternalism

AU - Tucker, Faye

N1 - This is the peer reviewed version of the following article: Tucker, F. (2016), Developing Autonomy and Transitional Paternalism. Bioethics, 30: 759–766. doi:10.1111/bioe.12280 which has been published in final form at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12280/abstract This article may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance With Wiley Terms and Conditions for self-archiving.

PY - 2016/11

Y1 - 2016/11

N2 - Adolescents, in many jurisdictions, have the power to consent to life saving treatment but not necessarily the power to refuse it. A recent defence of this asymmetry is Neil Manson's theory of ‘transitional paternalism’. Transitional paternalism holds that such asymmetries are by-products of sharing normative powers. However, sharing normative powers by itself does not entail an asymmetry because transitional paternalism can be implemented in two ways. Manson defends the asymmetry-generating version of transitional paternalism in the clinical context, arguing that it maximizes respect for adolescent autonomy. This article offers an alternative argument in favour of the asymmetry-generating form of transitional paternalism, one that makes appeal to obligations that individuals have to develop self-governance in others. We should share normative powers asymmetrically in the clinical context for three reasons. First, the asymmetric version of transitional paternalism takes seriously duties to support adolescents’ developing autonomy, alongside other duties that adults have to young people. It does so by enabling young people to be involved in important decisions that they would otherwise be excluded from. This is of value because participation of this sort is central to the cultivation of their self-governance. Second, only the asymmetric version gives young people a voice in respect of all clinical actions, and only the asymmetric version leaves open the possibility that the coarse lines of legislation might be ‘fine-tuned’ in individual cases. Third, the asymmetric sharing of normative powers is consistent with the kind of social arrangements that best support autonomy.

AB - Adolescents, in many jurisdictions, have the power to consent to life saving treatment but not necessarily the power to refuse it. A recent defence of this asymmetry is Neil Manson's theory of ‘transitional paternalism’. Transitional paternalism holds that such asymmetries are by-products of sharing normative powers. However, sharing normative powers by itself does not entail an asymmetry because transitional paternalism can be implemented in two ways. Manson defends the asymmetry-generating version of transitional paternalism in the clinical context, arguing that it maximizes respect for adolescent autonomy. This article offers an alternative argument in favour of the asymmetry-generating form of transitional paternalism, one that makes appeal to obligations that individuals have to develop self-governance in others. We should share normative powers asymmetrically in the clinical context for three reasons. First, the asymmetric version of transitional paternalism takes seriously duties to support adolescents’ developing autonomy, alongside other duties that adults have to young people. It does so by enabling young people to be involved in important decisions that they would otherwise be excluded from. This is of value because participation of this sort is central to the cultivation of their self-governance. Second, only the asymmetric version gives young people a voice in respect of all clinical actions, and only the asymmetric version leaves open the possibility that the coarse lines of legislation might be ‘fine-tuned’ in individual cases. Third, the asymmetric sharing of normative powers is consistent with the kind of social arrangements that best support autonomy.

KW - asymmetry of consent

KW - developing autonomy

KW - decision-making

KW - paternalism

KW - adolescence

KW - self-governance

U2 - 10.1111/bioe.12280

DO - 10.1111/bioe.12280

M3 - Journal article

VL - 30

SP - 759

EP - 766

JO - Bioethics

JF - Bioethics

SN - 1467-8519

IS - 9

ER -