Home > Research > Publications & Outputs > Subjective skewness of return as an explanation...
View graph of relations

Subjective skewness of return as an explanation of the optimal choice between gambles in cumulative prospect theory

Research output: Contribution to Journal/MagazineJournal articlepeer-review

Published

Standard

Subjective skewness of return as an explanation of the optimal choice between gambles in cumulative prospect theory. / Peel, D; Law, D.
In: Journal of Gambling Business and Economics, Vol. 2, No. 2, 2008, p. 97-107.

Research output: Contribution to Journal/MagazineJournal articlepeer-review

Harvard

APA

Vancouver

Peel D, Law D. Subjective skewness of return as an explanation of the optimal choice between gambles in cumulative prospect theory. Journal of Gambling Business and Economics. 2008;2(2):97-107. doi: 10.5750%2Fjgbe.v2i2.533

Author

Peel, D ; Law, D. / Subjective skewness of return as an explanation of the optimal choice between gambles in cumulative prospect theory. In: Journal of Gambling Business and Economics. 2008 ; Vol. 2, No. 2. pp. 97-107.

Bibtex

@article{ffa1c341de4746ca92cd0b9841beae41,
title = "Subjective skewness of return as an explanation of the optimal choice between gambles in cumulative prospect theory",
abstract = "Given that the expected return and variance of return of two gambles are equal the hypothesis that the gamble with the greater positive skewness of return will be chosen by an expected utility maximiser is appealing. However the hypothesis is not, in general, correct. Brockett and Garven (1998) and Brocket and Kahane (1992) demonstrate this both theoretically and by constructing counter examples.A particularly revealing example is the following one constructed by Brockett and Kahane. Gamble A has the two outcomes 2.45 and 7.49 with probabilities 0.5141 and 0.4859 respectively. Gamble B has the three outcomes 0, 4.947 and 10 with probabilities 0.12096, 0.750085 and 0.128955 respectively. Even though gamble A exhibits lower expected return, a higher variance and lower positive skewness than gamble B it is preferred to gamble B by an expected utility maximiser on the basis of any standard utility function such as power, log or exponential. Consequently in this example of theirs the expected utility maximiser exhibits an aversion to higher expected return and higher skewness and a preference for higher variance. As noted by Brockett and Kahane these results cannot be dismissed as decision makers “trading” variance for mean or skewness or having a strange idiosyncratic utility function.",
author = "D Peel and D Law",
year = "2008",
doi = "10.5750%2Fjgbe.v2i2.533",
language = "English",
volume = "2",
pages = "97--107",
journal = "Journal of Gambling Business and Economics",
issn = "1751-8008",
number = "2",

}

RIS

TY - JOUR

T1 - Subjective skewness of return as an explanation of the optimal choice between gambles in cumulative prospect theory

AU - Peel, D

AU - Law, D

PY - 2008

Y1 - 2008

N2 - Given that the expected return and variance of return of two gambles are equal the hypothesis that the gamble with the greater positive skewness of return will be chosen by an expected utility maximiser is appealing. However the hypothesis is not, in general, correct. Brockett and Garven (1998) and Brocket and Kahane (1992) demonstrate this both theoretically and by constructing counter examples.A particularly revealing example is the following one constructed by Brockett and Kahane. Gamble A has the two outcomes 2.45 and 7.49 with probabilities 0.5141 and 0.4859 respectively. Gamble B has the three outcomes 0, 4.947 and 10 with probabilities 0.12096, 0.750085 and 0.128955 respectively. Even though gamble A exhibits lower expected return, a higher variance and lower positive skewness than gamble B it is preferred to gamble B by an expected utility maximiser on the basis of any standard utility function such as power, log or exponential. Consequently in this example of theirs the expected utility maximiser exhibits an aversion to higher expected return and higher skewness and a preference for higher variance. As noted by Brockett and Kahane these results cannot be dismissed as decision makers “trading” variance for mean or skewness or having a strange idiosyncratic utility function.

AB - Given that the expected return and variance of return of two gambles are equal the hypothesis that the gamble with the greater positive skewness of return will be chosen by an expected utility maximiser is appealing. However the hypothesis is not, in general, correct. Brockett and Garven (1998) and Brocket and Kahane (1992) demonstrate this both theoretically and by constructing counter examples.A particularly revealing example is the following one constructed by Brockett and Kahane. Gamble A has the two outcomes 2.45 and 7.49 with probabilities 0.5141 and 0.4859 respectively. Gamble B has the three outcomes 0, 4.947 and 10 with probabilities 0.12096, 0.750085 and 0.128955 respectively. Even though gamble A exhibits lower expected return, a higher variance and lower positive skewness than gamble B it is preferred to gamble B by an expected utility maximiser on the basis of any standard utility function such as power, log or exponential. Consequently in this example of theirs the expected utility maximiser exhibits an aversion to higher expected return and higher skewness and a preference for higher variance. As noted by Brockett and Kahane these results cannot be dismissed as decision makers “trading” variance for mean or skewness or having a strange idiosyncratic utility function.

U2 - 10.5750%2Fjgbe.v2i2.533

DO - 10.5750%2Fjgbe.v2i2.533

M3 - Journal article

VL - 2

SP - 97

EP - 107

JO - Journal of Gambling Business and Economics

JF - Journal of Gambling Business and Economics

SN - 1751-8008

IS - 2

ER -